by ADAM CURRAN REID
Many thanks to Josh for the opportunity to publish on his blog. What
follows is a slightly revised and expanded version of my original remarks in
response to "In Defense of Fishing," along with a lengthier summary of our
subsequent exchange over email. Comments are welcome and encouraged.
My original response
Hey Josh. Thanks for sharing your thoughts. As an ethical vegan
[1], I obviously
disagree fundamentally with much of what you say, even while I appreciate how
honest, open, and morally serious you are in trying to work through your
thoughts on these issues in such a systematic way. What follows are just a few
general comments and reactions I had while reading your piece, very much
offered in the spirit of friendly inquiry.
At a general level, I think you’re absolutely right to note that
considerations about ‘fairness,’ the environment, and the like can only go so
far in thinking one’s way through to the moral core of the issue. As you
rightly point out, the more pressing question seems to be whether there could
be
any defensible justification for killing animals (or as I
would say, using animals in any way, shape, or form) — particularly in view of
the fact that we can (again, as you rightly note) live perfectly healthy, happy
lives without doing so.
[2]
My response is that there simply is no so such justification. Animals
are not things; nor are they resources or property. Animals are
selves;
beings with a subjective experience of the world, a capacity to feel pain,
pleasure, fear, safety, confusion, disorientation, etc. (i.e. states that are
‘like something’ to be in). Granted, most, perhaps all, non-human animals lack
the requisite cognitive sophistication to conceptualize, much less articulate,
any of this (which is precisely why they need human advocates), but this
shouldn’t, in my view, stop us from recognizing that these are beings for whom,
and to whom, quality of life matters (I include in the phrase ‘quality of life’
here the basic interest in continuing to have one). I would argue that these
considerations alone suffice to ground the strong animal rights position that
animals ought to be viewed as having a fundamental moral standing, up to and
including a comprehensive package of basic rights (first and foremost being the
right not to be killed, enslaved, experimented on, and so on). Obviously this
is meant to be taken only as a snapshot of — not an argument for — the strong
animal rights position; if anyone is looking for an argument, I’d recommend
Gary Francione, or my former
professor, Will Kymlicka (specifically, the first few chapters of
Zoopolis:
A
Political Theory of Animal Rights, co-authored with Sue Donaldson).
But getting back to the question at hand — why, or on what grounds,
might we think it morally defensible to kill animals, given that, let’s face
it, we really don’t
need to — to my mind the most important
consideration here is just that; necessity. As long-time vegan, animal rights
activist, and Rutgers professor (of law and philosophy) Gary Francione often
points out, there is an important if underappreciated sense in which many of
us, perhaps even most of us, actually are vegan (in spirit) already. This is
the sense in which we already accept (or, one hopes, we
would accept,
upon reflection) the principle that animals ought not to be made to
suffer
unnecessarily. Here’s the catch: however we go on to unpack
the details of what it means for something to be ‘necessary’ in this context,
it seems clear that even the most minimal construal is going to have to
preclude anything whose justification appeals solely to reasons based in
convenience, entertainment, recreation, pleasure, and so on. The trouble is,
these really are the only reasons we have for continuing to use animals. [This
is a rough paraphrase of something he said during an interview once; I am
unable to recall the exact source, but I'm sure it can be found on his
website].
One might object at this point by claiming that there are deeper,
socio-historical reasons in support of our legitimately using animals — reasons
deriving from cultural or religious traditions, for example — in short, reasons
which are not wholly
reducible to convenience, pleasure, and
the like. In my view, this objection amounts to little more than what
philosophers refer to as the "naturalistic fallacy" (a.k.a. the "is/ought" problem), which points out that one
cannot legitimately derive an "ought" (e.g. we
should continue
using animals) from an "is" (e.g. we
have always used animals).
We should also bear in mind here that we would hardly accept, as a legitimate
moral justification for, e.g., sexism or slavery, the claim that practices of
this sort are culturally prescribed and/or religiously enshrined. To the
contrary, we would insist that cultural and religious traditions that enjoin
such practices should transform — indeed conform — to the universal moral truth
that men and women are entitled to equal concern and respect, that people are
not property, and so on. Vegans, of the strong animal rights persuasion,
maintain that the same goes for using animals.
[3]
Getting back to the necessity, or lack thereof, of using/killing
animals: though not directly in response to this, at one point you talk about
the fallacy of supposing that the
only rewards of killing a
fish are to be found in the enjoyment of a tasty meal; noting that there are in
fact a great many other rewards to be had. You then list amongst such rewards
the satisfaction of, e.g. knowing where the fish lived, how it was caught,
killed, roughly what its diet was like, etc. Since these are only going to be
counted as ‘rewards’ if one
already thinks it
morally permissible to kill (and eat) fish, I don’t view them as having any
real countervailing weight against the unnecessary suffering injunction
introduced above (for these same reasons, I would personally also dismiss the
satisfaction of feeling connected to the land, harvesting one’s own food, etc.
since these are all pleasures one can obtain without using and/or killing
animals). You then discuss the pleasures of feeling engrossed with nature, of
escaping the frenzy of urban climes for the serenity and peace of just being
out on the river, and so forth. Though I personally found this to be more
interesting, you won’t be surprised to hear that I’m not inclined to view this
as having any justificatory force whatsoever; again, the simple reason being
that this just is not something whose attainment requires killing animals
(hiking, canoeing, and nature photography are probably the most obvious
alternatives that spring to mind).
RE: your discussion of the idea of a ‘moral remainder’ or ‘moral
residue’ — more precisely, your remarks about the acknowledgement of, and
attitude toward, this remainder as the mark that distinguishes the venerable
from the despicable angler — my thoughts are less clear. Certainly I do
recognize that there is
a difference between the two types of
anglers you describe (presumably a moral difference, though I’m not sure just
what sort of difference this is); though, as a vegan, I’m more inclined to
gloss the distinction as one between the infliction of more vs. less harm.
Still, trivially, recognizing the fact that less harm is obviously preferable
to more harm (in whatever context) is fully compatible with questioning (or, in
my case, denying) the
need for any such harm to begin with.
I suppose the parts I had the most trouble with were your remarks about
solemnity, deep respect, and attitudes of this sort in the context of killing
and eating fish. At one point you mention how one might even think of appropriately
reverent, ‘humane’ killing as a kind of sacrament. But to whom (or what), and
for whom (or what) is this sacrament undertaken in the first place? Oneself?
The fish? In any case, why does the act need to take place at all? I was
similarly perplexed by your suggestion that part of this attitude can be
thought of in terms of gratitude or thankfulness. At one point you say "one
might thank the fish for giving up its life?" I realize, of course, that this
isn’t an especially novel notion, as it is no doubt part of many traditional
hunter-gatherer cultures. The trouble is, it’s incoherent — or so, at least, I
would argue. In the first instance, the fish does not ‘give up its life,’
rather, its life is
taken. Moreover, the fish obviously lacks the
cognitive capacity to appreciate the thought that its death, in whatever small
measure, contributes (as nourishment) to the aspirationally admirable life of
the angler who kills it; nor can the fish acknowledge, much less accept, the
angler’s gratitude, any more than it can refuse consent to being recreationally
jerked and tugged around by a hook, attached to a line, caught in its lip. So
while I do think that you’ve hit on, and usefully emphasized, an important idea
with that of the ‘moral remainder’ of killing fish (and presumably, animals in
general), I would argue that, rather than search for ways we might offset or
discharge this remainder, the truly admirable thing would be to simply not
incur it in the first place.
Further Clarification
Following my initial response (in the comments section) to his post,
Josh and I engaged in a lively and very fruitful email exchange; an exchange
that afforded me a number of opportunities to clarify my position by responding
to some important questions and objections that he raised. I suspect that we
will have more to say about these issues in subsequent posts, but for now
here’s the gist of it.
The first objection Josh raised was to note that, even accepting the ‘no
unnecessary suffering’ injunction for the sake of argument, it’s not clear why
(on my view) killing animals should count as inherently wrong since, simply
put, this needn’t involve suffering at all. Josh writes,
"Suppose I grant for
the nonce that one ought not to cause unnecessary suffering. Even so, it seems
to me you still lack an adequate basis for claiming that I ought not to kill
anything, that is, not just fish, but also bears and geese and people and so
on. The reason is just that death needn't involve any suffering. For one thing,
you don't have to cause an organism to suffer prior to its death in order to
make it die. As a case in point, consider this story. When I was much younger,
I used to go deer hunting with my grandpa. Once, when I was hunting with him, I
spotted a large buck within range and took aim. Shortly thereafter, the deer
turned toward me. I shot him through the trachea and spinal cord, breaking his
neck; he fell immediately. Thereafter, he didn't even twitch; he died
immediately, before he even knew he was in danger. It seems to me obvious that
that deer did not suffer prior to its death. And as for death itself, I don't
think one experiences one's death; indeed, how could one? As Wittgenstein says
(Tractatus, 6.4311), "Death is not an event in life." So how
could death itself involve any suffering? If I'm right that this deer did not
suffer when I killed it, then your principle is irrelevant and implies nothing
about the moral status of my action. If you want to claim that I ought not to
have done that, it seems to me you need to give me some other reason. I suspect
you probably have one, and if so, I'd be interested to know it."
I actually agree with most everything Josh says here. Certainly death
needn't be preceded by much, or even any, suffering. Death can sometimes occur
instantaneously (as his deer example illustrates); death, so to speak, needn't
always involve the experience of
dying.
Moving on to Wittgenstein (though I'm actually more familiar with this
from Thomas Nagel; see his essay "Death," in
Mortal Questions),
Josh and I are more or less in agreement here too: death is not a state of
experience; death, rather, is the cessation of
all experience.
Hence, by definition, no animal (fish, deer, human, etc.) experiences its own
death. Death is just the onset of nothingness; but even that is misleading,
since, again, there literally is no
subject that undergoes
this onset. So it looks like death, by its very nature, cannot
straightforwardly be considered a harm, since a necessary condition of
something even so much as counting as a harm — namely, the existence of a
subject to whom the harm is attached — is entirely absent. Therefore, strictly
speaking, no animal can be harmed by their own death. Or so, at least, one
could argue.
Again, I more or less agree with all of this (or at least, for the sake
of argument, am happy to go along with it). If I came off in my initial
response as implying that I take the wrongfulness of killing fish (or any other
animal) to be essentially or primarily a matter of the wrongfulness of
inflicting
felt harm, then I apologize, for I was not being
clear.
Two points: the first is that my general philosophical leaning on the
question of "how, and if so, in what sense, can a person be harmed by
their own death?" is basically just Nagel's view (at least, I
think it's
his view): roughly, the badness or 'harmfulness' of death consists in the
denial of possible future experience; thus we should say that it is the
pre-mortem person who
is harmed by their own death, because this is the subject who, after all, is
robbed of future existence. One could argue that the same reasoning applies
straightforwardly in the case of non-human animals as well: since it is
independently plausible to think that all animals have a basic interest in
continuing to exist
[4], in killing one, we
are violating a basic interest, and in violating this interest, we are harming
a pre-mortem self.
But this is already far too intellectual and, in my view, not really
necessary anyway; which brings me to my second point. As a vegan
abolitionist
[5], my view is this:
because fundamental interests
[6] are
species-independent,
membership in a particular species is not a prerequisite for membership in the
class of beings to which fundamental moral concern ought to be extended. Simply
put, the moral reasons in virtue of which it’s wrong for a human to kill
another human — even in such a way as to ensure the death is as painless as
possible; indeed, even instantaneous — are equally reasons for thinking this is
impermissible in the case of non-human animals.
[7] As I see it,
the alternative double standard is ultimately just speciesism of one form or another.
Josh’s second question comes in the form of an interesting
dilemma-posing thought experiment. He writes:
"I got the impression
from your original comments that you think that, if it were necessary for
humans to eat meat, in the sense that, if we didn't, we would fail to get some
essential nutrient and so eventually die, it would be permissible to eat
animals. Am I right about that? If I am, then I wonder what you think about
this. Suppose that it were necessary for us to eat meat in this sense. Would it
then be permissible for us to eat one another? If you say no, as it seems to me
you should, it seems to me that you are according humans and non-human animals
different sets of basic rights, which, I take it, is something you want to
avoid."
This is, indeed, a tricky question, one that’s been
exercising me for a while now, ever since Josh first posed it to me. In response, I would begin by directing the reader’s attention to an
instructive passage from Kymlicka and Donaldson
[8], a passage which I believe holds the key to framing
a plausible vegan response to the dilemma Josh
poses.
"...[T]his
term [inviolability] does not mean that basic rights are absolute and
exceptionless. This is not true in either the human or animal case, as in
cases of self-defence. Human beings have an inviolable right to life, but
killing another human being is permissible if it is done out of self-defence or
necessity. So, too, with animals. There is also a historical dimension
to the issue of inviolability. At different stages of human history, or
in particular contexts, humans have had to harm and/or kill animals in order to
survive. In that sense, too, basic inviolable rights are not absolute or
unconditional.
"This
raises a more general point about the nature of justice: namely, that it only
applies in certain circumstances — what Rawls (following Hume) calls the
'circumstances of justice.' Ought implies can: humans only owe justice to
each other when they are in fact able to respect each other's rights without
jeopardizing their own existence. Rawls calls this the requirement of
'moderate scarcity:' justice is necessary because there isn't an unlimited pool
of resources such that everyone can have everything that they want; but for
justice to be possible,
the competition for resources must be moderate rather than severe, in the sense
that I can afford to recognize your legitimate claims without undermining my
own existence.
"We can
contrast this with what are sometimes called 'lifeboat cases,' when there is
too little food or shelter for all to survive. In these lifeboat
conditions, the most extreme actions may need to be contemplated. In
order to avoid everyone on the boat dying, one person may be sacrificed, or
sacrifice themselves, and various proposals have been made about how to decide
who should live and who should die. But the existence of such extreme
lifeboat cases tells us nothing about the basic rights we owe each other in the
normal case where the circumstances of justice do apply. In moderate
scarcity, rather than lifeboat cases, murdering other humans for food or
shelter is wrong."
(Underlining added)
The potential application of these remarks to the case Josh
describes is clear enough: the circumstances of justice, one could argue,
simply do not apply in a world like this; indeed, to a vegan, the world itself
is essentially just one big survival situation (morally speaking). In such a world, we would have no choice but
to kill and eat animals in order to survive.
To be sure, this is not (yet) an altogether
satisfying response; though it does, I think, contain the makings of one.
Though promising as far as it goes, the problem is that, as it stands, it does not really
address the full force of Josh’s challenge, since now the question has become:
in virtue of what, by vegan lights, are we justified in viewing the
circumstances of justice as continuing to hold between one another, but
not between ourselves and non-human
animals? Appeals to ‘necessity’ are no
use here either, since our survival in this world could equally be obtained by
killing (and eating) one another. Why,
then, should we not regard this as equally morally permissible? Indeed, wouldn’t our failure to do so
constitute the very
essence of
speciesism?
The
short answer, I think, is: yes. To
understand ourselves as no longer in the circumstances of justice with
non-human animals in such a case, even while retaining this standing with our
fellow humans,
would amount to a form
of speciesism; I cannot see a way around this. Now, if you are
vegan, this might appear to be a somewhat awkward point to concede; thought it is not, I think, a
damning one, for reasons that should become clear in a moment. But first, consider the following alternative. Suppose one were to argue that
it actually
would be morally
permissible to kill and eat humans in
such a world, stressing, all the while, the following qualification: the equal
permissibility of killing human and
non-human animals in this scenario does not
automatically
entail that one is
morally
obligated to show no
preference between the two. If this much is
accepted, then perhaps vegans could consistently maintain that, in the scenario
Josh describes, preference could legitimately be shown for killing non-human
animals (over humans) in order to survive?
If the former strategy appears somewhat awkward, this one is bound to seem downright
lawyerly in its verbal maneuvering, and I doubt very much that there are many
who would be persuaded by it. At the moment, then, perhaps the only thing one can say
for sure is that, if you are a vegan, such a world would be morally tragic
whatever the correct response turns out to be.
As it happens, I myself feel that the first strategy is the correct response. In saying this, however, I am opening the door to a very natural objection. In particular, some might insist that my countenancing speciesism in this hypothetical scenario fatally undermines any supposed reasons of
principle I might cite for rejecting it in
this world. The claim, then, is that I cannot
consistently have it both ways; what goes for the one case, goes for the other. This objection is overblown. To see that this is so, note that, by itself, the fact that
some, probably most, vegans (myself included) would feel compelled in such a
case to accept solidarity with their own species over countenancing the equal
permissibility of killing human and non-human animals really lends nothing at all in the way of support to the strong conclusion that we are secretly, deep
down, tacit speciesists — any more than my choosing to kill a complete stranger
over my partner in an extreme ‘lifeboat’ type of scenario implies that,
deep down, part of me harbours a secret desire to kill strangers. In short, if my response to Josh’s dilemma
reveals anything, it is that speciesism, of the sort we are considering here,
is nothing if not a tragic, last-ditch, moral
compromise that vegans would view themselves as forced to make. On that note, it struck me that this
scenario is potentially very interesting to consider from the perspective of Josh’s
notion (sub Hursthouse) of the ‘moral remainder,’ or ‘moral residue.’ In such a
world, it seems to me (and, if I’m not mistaken, to Josh as well) that our
killing/eating behavior would accrue an enormous moral debt in just the sense
he describes in his post. Of course, my
initial suggestion — that the truly admirable thing to do would be to simply
not incur such debt in the first place — would not apply here. Indeed, the
global condition of our species in such a world would seem to be one of moral
emergency; the cost of survival itself involving a sort of ‘moral tax’ that we
would have no choice but to pay. One response would be to stress that we have a
standing duty to
bring about the circumstances of justice
where they don’t currently obtain.
[9] So, with this in mind, in response to Josh’s
dilemma vegans can and should maintain that, however we understand our moral
responsibilities toward non-human animals in the immediate interim in such a world, our
long-term responsibility is clear: we would be under a moral obligation to seek
out alternative means of survival; means that do not require us to kill animals.
What’s more, given our considerable ingenuity as a species,
this would presumably be well within our reach.
Most important of all, however, is to bear in mind Kymilcka
and Donaldson’s final point in the passage above — which is simply to remind us
that, whatever our feelings about what we might, or even must, do in these
hypothetical ‘moral emergency’ scenarios, such philosophizing really tells us
little to nothing about what we should do in the here and now. In other words, (thankfully!) we do not live
in the sort of world Josh raises for consideration; it is
not necessary to kill and eat animals to survive. In
this
world, I submit, we
do find ourselves
in the circumstances of justice with animals.
[10]
In closing, and at the risk of sounding too clichéd, I would just add
that it really is the essence of philosophical inquiry to examine one’s own
life first and foremost. I’m not sure I’d go as far as Socrates in saying that
the unexamined life is not worth
living, but I do feel that we owe
it to ourselves to examine, and re-examine, our convictions (and our
assumptions) from time to time and, most importantly, be prepared to revise, or
even reject, them should we come to feel that, on reflection, they are no
longer worthy of our continued allegiance. This is particularly important with
respect to our consumptive decisions, since, arguably, these are the decisions
that have the most direct impact in the world — not only on our own health and
well-being (physical, spiritual, moral), but also on that of the planet and,
indeed, the other beings (human and non) with whom we
share this
world. At the end of the day, of course, this is all just words; and words can
only take us so far. If anyone is interested in learning more about these
issues, I would highly recommend the documentary film
A Peaceable Kingdom: The Journey Home — which, unlike
some films of its kind, is every bit as powerful and tastefully done as it is
watchable and (for the most part) non-graphic. On a personal note, I would add
that this film is what compelled me to go vegan, by helping me to find the
courage to realize that my own consumptive behavior (as a vegetarian of almost
ten years) was still fundamentally out of sync with what I innately knew to be
right, but had long ignored.
Thanks again to Josh for the opportunity to post my response on his
blog, and, of course, for the interesting (and ongoing!) debate about these
important issues.
[1] By "ethical vegan" I mean someone whose veganism derives from the
belief that animals have an intrinsic moral status as beings that ought always
to be treated as ends in themselves. The term is sometimes used to
differentiate vegans of this sort from those whose veganism is motivated by,
e.g., health concerns, religious prescription, or environmental reasons.
[2] The truth of this notwithstanding, one might still wonder what veganism
would entail if (contrary to fact) it actually was
not possible
to be at least as healthy on a balanced, nutritionally responsible vegan diet
as an omnivore diet; that is to say, if being vegan meant being less healthy
overall than nutritionally responsible omnivores. This has actually come up in
conversation a couple times for me and, though I confess I've not really
thought it through in any great depth, my gut reaction has always been to say
that one ought to still be vegan. Some vegans might think that, even if this is
the right response generally speaking, there is in principle
some threshold
(of unhealthiness) beyond which it would simply be
unreasonable for
veganism to imply that one ought nevertheless be prepared to accept. Then
again, other vegans might deny this. Thankfully, this scenario is
counterfactual only; it
is possible to be perfectly healthy on
a nutritionally responsible vegan diet. But even so, it behooves vegans to
consider it carefully, since we should all of us, vegan and non, aspire to
better understand the logic of our own convictions. At the moment, I confess
that I'm not sure where I stand on this 'threshold' question.
[3] A more promising objection strategy (according to some) is to stress that, even granting for the sake of argument that we ought not to use animals for any of the reasons considered so far, the case of medical experimentation is not as clear-cut. Here, one might argue (indeed, even some self-styled ethical ‘vegans’ argue this), we
are morally justified in using/killing animals since, had we
not used animals in this way, many humans would surely have died over the years (and, indeed, would die in the future), bereft of the life-saving medicines and treatments we would otherwise have acquired. In short, one might argue that we have an
overriding interest based in our own survival (which, presumably, is as
necessary a reason as any) that justifies using animals; simply put, the alternative is a ‘sacrifice’ we should not have to make. The right response to this, I think, is clear enough. Here I defer to Will Kymlicka and Sue Donaldson, who elaborate the response as follows. On p.44 (Kindle edition) of their book
Zoopolis:
A Political Theory of Animal Rights (Oxford University Press, 2011), they write:
"...[T]o view this as a sacrifice is already to misunderstand the moral situation. After all, there are countless medical technologies and medical advances that don’t exist today because we refuse to use human subjects for invasive experiments. It is hard to overestimate the advances that medical science could have made by now if researchers had been able to use human subjects, rather than imperfect animal stand-ins. Yet we do not view this as a sacrifice. We do not wake up every day lamenting all that untapped knowledge; we are not bitter about the restriction on human subjects that has so hampered medical advance; we do not worry that an overly squeamish attitude about respecting the rights of a few humans is standing in the way of longer and healthier lives for the rest of us. Indeed, anyone who viewed prohibitions on using humans as research subjects as a sacrifice would be seen as morally perverse. We fully understand, in the human context, that medical knowledge must advance within ethical boundaries, or it simply isn’t knowledge that we have a right to. This may force us to be more creative about how we learn, or to be more patient in waiting for results. Either way, it’s not something we view as a sacrifice. It’s a recognition that a world in which better or longer lives for the many are purchased by sacrificing the few is not a world worth living in.
"It will require a huge adjustment for societies to accept that medical knowledge gained by harming and killing animals is not knowledge to which we are entitled. But the costs of the adjustment would be temporary. After a few decades in which new practices became customary, and a new generation of researchers trained, animal experimentation would be perceived much as human experimentation is viewed today. Its prohibition would not be viewed as a cost, just as the absence of human experimentation is not viewed as a cost."
[4] As Francione puts it (paraphrase), "To say that a being who is
sentient has no interest in continuing to live is like saying that a being with
eyes has no interest in continuing to see." I am not sure exactly where he says
this, but it can be found on his website.
[5]Vegan abolitionism is the view that there simply are no grounds for
our using, and killing, animals period. Abolitionism thus contrasts with what
is known in the literature as "welfarism;" which is the view that there is
nothing inherently wrong, in principle, with using, and even killing, animals
for human ends, provided that we do so in a way that is ‘humane.’ Peter Singer
is a good example of a well-known contemporary welfarist; Gary Francione is
perhaps the most well-known vegan abolitionist.
[6] Roughly, our interests in not being abused, enslaved, physically
exploited, killed, eaten, and so on.
[7] It’s conceivable that one could object that part of the problem here
is that, all due respect to Nagel, it actually is
not entirely
clear just what’s morally wrong with painlessly, instantaneously, killing a
person — provided, of course, the victim has no prior knowledge of their
immanent death. To be sure, it’s hard to imagine anyone seriously raising such
a concern beyond the context of the philosophical armchair, but nevermind
that. The response is clear enough: we don’t need to know, with exhaustive
philosophical precision,
why something is wrong in order to
know
that it’s wrong — and we certainly do know
that it’s
wrong, other things being equal, to kill someone.
[8] Will Kymlicka and Sue Donaldson,
Zoopolis:
A
Political Theory of Animal Rights (Oxford University Press, 2011), pp.
40-41; Kindle edition.
[9] This point is owed, once again, to Kymlicka and Donaldson (Ibid.)
[10] Kymlicka and Donaldson allow that there may be isolated
communities of humans (in
this world) whose survival depends
on hunting animals; such communities, they say, might plausibly be regarded as
not within the circumstances of justice with animals. (Ibid.)
© Adam Curran Reid 2013. All Rights Reserved.